![]() |
|||
The Myth of Democratic Peace: Theoretical
and Empirical Shortcomings of the "Democratic Peace Theory"
|
|||
Binnur Ozkececi-Taner*
|
|||
The study of international affairs should be understood as a protracted
competition between the realist and liberal traditions. Although not a
monolithic paradigm itself, realism depicts that international affairs
is a struggle for power among self-interested states and is generally
pessimistic about the prospects for eliminating conflict and war. This
paradigm dominated the field in the Cold War years because it provided
simple, yet powerful explanations for war, alliances, imperialism, and
obstacles to cooperation and because its emphasis on competition was consistent
with the central features of the American-Soviet rivalry. The principal
challenge to realism comes from a broad family of liberal theories, which
does not constitute a monolithic view, either. While one strand of liberal
thought has argued that economic interdependence would discourage states
from using force against each other because warfare would threaten each
side's prosperity,(1) the second, more recent liberal view has suggested
that international institutions and regimes could overcome selfish state
behaviours, mainly by encouraging states to forego immediate gains for
the greater benefits of enduring cooperation.(2) The third view, however,
probably has had the most popularity in both scholarship and policy circles,
which sees the spread of democracy as the key to world peace, based on
the claim that democratic states are inherently more peaceful than authoritarian
states. This essay is about the third variant of liberalist thought, namely
the "democratic peace." The essay will review the "democratic
peace" literature critically and will argue that the "democratic
peace" is theoretically and empirically overdetermined. "Democratic Peace" Theory Defined: The theoretical foundations of the 'democratic peace' proposition, labeled
by Bruce Russett, can be divided into 1) the monadic proposition and 2)
the dyadic proposition.(5) Monadic and dyadic interpretations of the democratic
peace differ in the extent to which the regime type of the target state
is considered important. Monadic proposition simply suggests that the
more democratic the state, the less violent its behaviour toward all other
states, including both democracies and non-democracies, will be.(6) Most
quantitative works done on the monadic proposition seem to have supported
the argument. Rummel argued that democracies are in fact the most pacific
of regimes because costly and unsuccessful wars can increase a leader's
chances of losing his or her position, which makes leaders in democracies
less likely to initiate wars that are expected to be severely violent
or that are likely to have high overall costs.(7) Zeev Maoz and Nasrin
Abdolai have also found that democratic states are less likely to escalate
disputes into wars,(8) which has been confirmed by others,(9) who suggested
that domestic political structures constrain democratic leaders from choosing
war as a foreign policy. Jack Snyder's qualitative analysis of democratic
state behaviour also supported the monadic proposition, which argued that
consolidated [added by the author] democratic states are less likely to
extend their commitments beyond their capabilities; democratic institutions
assert an identifiable pacifying effect, regardless of the domestic regime
type of others.(10) According to the proponents of the dyadic model, which has usually been
seen as more accurate proposition in any discussion on "democratic
peace," on the other hand, democratic states do not wage war with
each other while they are no less war-prone than other types of states.(11)
In opposition to the monadic proposition, this proposition suggests that
the regime type of the opponent will crucially affect war decision and
democratic states can be war-prone when facing non-democratic counterparts.
Hostility toward non-democratic states is more likely because it is easier
to mobilize public support for military actions because non-democratic
governments are "in a state of aggression with their own people,"
which makes "their foreign relations deeply suspect for democratic
governments."(12) The "democratic peace" proponents suggest two explanations
why democracies do not fight war with each other. The first explanation
lies in the structural/institutional constraints.(13) According to the
structural/institutional model, democracies keep mutual peace because
of the constitutional checks and balances that tie the hands of decision-makers
and the whole complex of structure of democratic civil society. The institutional
constraints on a leader's actions signify that the decision-makers are
likely to face high political costs for using force in its diplomacy.(14)
Moreover, democratically elected leaders are unable to act quickly and
this cautious foreign policy behaviour reduces the likelihood that a conflict
will escalate to war.(15) The second reason why democracies are considered
more peaceful is related to the understanding that democracies have shared
cultural/democratic norms among themselves. According to this argument,
democratic political culture encourages peaceful means of internal conflict
resolution, which "come to apply across national boundaries toward
other democratic states,"(16) and the decision-makers are in the
habit of expecting that their actions will be reciprocated by the other
democratic states. The cultural/democratic norms argument has been considered
as more robust and explanatory than the institutional/structural explanations
since the latter is silent on the issue of democratic public's willingness
to fight wars against non-democracies,(17) while some scholars have argued
that the normative and institutional arguments are not mutually exclusive;
they work in "tandem."(18) Deconstructing "Democratic Peace" Theory: One can also dispute the fact that democracy produces peace by claiming
that it is the peace that produces democracy.(29) This argument presents
a new problem to the "democratic peace" theory, suggesting an
unclear causal link. Furthermore, as Hermann and Kegley suggested,"democratic
peace" theorists have overlooked instances of coercive actions short
of formal war by suggesting that there were at least fifteen incidents
of unequivocally democratic states intervening with military force against
other democracies.(30) This is a result of "democratic peace"
theorists not making any explicit claims about the sources of non-democratic
war or peace, land their total negligence, if not ignorance, of constraints
on the authoritarian leaders.(31) More seriously, however, "democratic peace" theorists cannot
adequately account for the tendency towards was in democratizing countries,
especially after the end of the Cold War. As it has been demonstrated
many times since the late 1980s, democratizing states are most often very
volatile and dangerous and, thus more inclined to fight wars "than
are mature democracies or stable autocracies."(32) The "rocky
transitional period" to democratization may make countries more aggressive
and war-prone due to not only domestic competition but also utilization
of nationalistic feelings by political leadership and mass public support
for aggression. If the "democratic peace" theorists would want
to make their cases more persuasive, then, those authors should be more
attentive to what is going on in newly democratizing countries and modify,
not necessarily change, some of their propositions. The 'democratic peace' theory also underemphasizes the role of the political
leadership. The scholars of the 'democratic peace' theory do not ask the
questions of how different leaders view national goals and how they try
to achieve them. This neglect downplays the role that extraordinary individuals
often play in war and peace decision-making.(33) Literature from political
psychology has suggested that when we take into account what happens within
the decision-making process in democracies, institutional and cultural
obstacles may not always restrain what decisions are reached, "making
democracy and peace more complex and nuanced than is conventionally pictured."(34)
Although regime characteristics constantly push for the election of leaders
who "respect and respond to democratic values," as Hermann &
Kegley have argued, ideologically driven leaders can come to power, i.e.,
Reagan in the US, Thatcher in Great Britain. These leaders may either
challenge institutional and cultural constraints or be less open to incoming
information in order to maintain their positions and/or divert attention
from more disturbing issues. Additionally, even if we accept that institutional
and cultural explanations account for the "democratic peace,"
the questions of how these constraints and the nature of other countries,
whether they are democratic or not, are perceived by the leadership are
not answered by the "democratic peace" literature. Conclusion: * Ph.D.Candidate, Department of Political Science at Syracuse University's Maxwell School of Citizenship and Public Affairs; Research Associate at Syracuse University's Global Affairs Institute; Editorial Assistant, International Studies Review. NOTES |